Advanced Calculus (I)

63  Download (0)

Full text

(1)

Advanced Calculus (I)

WEN-CHING LIEN

Department of Mathematics National Cheng Kung University

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(2)

3.4 Uniform continuity

Definition

Let E be a nonempty subset of R and f :ER.Then f is said to be uniformly continuous on E (notation: f :ER is uniformly continuous) if and only if for every ǫ >0 there is aδ >0 such that

|x −a| < δ and x,aE imply |f(x) −f(a)| < ǫ.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(3)

3.4 Uniform continuity

Definition

Let E be a nonempty subset of R and f :ER.Then f is said to be uniformly continuous on E (notation: f :ER is uniformly continuous) if and only if for every ǫ >0 there is aδ >0 such that

|x −a| < δ and x,aE imply |f(x) −f(a)| < ǫ.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(4)

Example:

Show that f(x) =x2is not uniformly continuous on R.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(5)

Example:

Show that f(x) =x2is not uniformly continuous on R.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(6)

Lemma:

Suppose that ER and f :ER is uniformly continuous. If xnE is Cauchy, then f(xn)is Cauchy.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(7)

Lemma:

Suppose that ER and f :ER is uniformly continuous. If xnE is Cauchy, then f(xn)is Cauchy.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(8)

Theorem

Suppose that I is a closed, bounded interval. If f :IR is continuous on I, then f is uniformly continuous on I.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(9)

Theorem

Suppose that I is a closed, bounded interval. If f :IR is continuous on I, then f is uniformly continuous on I.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(10)

Proof:

Suppose to the contrary that f is continuous but not uniformly continuous on I Then there is anǫ0 >0 and points xn,ynI such that|xnyn| <1/n and

(10) |f(xn) −f(yn)| ≥ ǫ0, nN.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(11)

Proof:

Suppose to the contrary that f is continuous but not uniformly continuous on I Then there is anǫ0 >0 and points xn,ynI such that|xnyn| <1/n and

(10) |f(xn) −f(yn)| ≥ ǫ0, nN.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(12)

Proof:

Suppose to the contrary that f is continuous but not uniformly continuous on I Then there is anǫ0 >0 and points xn,ynI such that|xnyn| <1/n and

(10) |f(xn) −f(yn)| ≥ ǫ0, nN.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(13)

Proof:

Suppose to the contrary that f is continuous but not uniformly continuous on I Then there is anǫ0 >0 and points xn,ynI such that|xnyn| <1/n and

(10) |f(xn) −f(yn)| ≥ ǫ0, nN.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(14)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(15)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence{xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(16)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly,the sequence {ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(17)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(18)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly,the sequence {ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6=f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(19)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6=f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(20)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0;i.e., f(x) 6=f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(21)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6=f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(22)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0;i.e., f(x) 6=f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N,so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(23)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y .Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(24)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N,so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y),a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(25)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y .Therefore, f(x) =f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(26)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y),a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(27)

By the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem and the Comparison Theorem, the sequence {xn}has a subsequence, say xnk, that converges, as k → ∞, to some xI. Similarly, the sequence{ynk}k∈Nhas a convergent subsequence, say ynkj, that converges, as j → ∞, to some y ∈I. Since xnkjx as j → ∞and f is continuous, it follows from (10) that|f(x) −f(y)| ≥ ǫ0; i.e., f(x) 6= f(y). But|xnyn| <1/n for all n∈N, so Theorem 2.9 (the Squeeze Theorem) implies that x =y . Therefore, f(x) = f(y), a contradiction. 2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(28)

Theorem

Let(a,b) be a bounded, open, nonempty interval and f : (a,b) →R. Then f is uniformly continuous on(a,b)if and only if f can be extended continuously to [a,b], i.e., if and only if there is a continuous function g : [a,b] → R that satifies

(11) f(x) =g(x), x ∈ (a,b).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(29)

Theorem

Let(a,b) be a bounded, open, nonempty interval and f : (a,b) →R. Then f is uniformly continuous on(a,b)if and only if f can be extended continuously to [a,b], i.e., if and only if there is a continuous function g : [a,b] → R that satifies

(11) f(x) =g(x), x ∈ (a,b).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(30)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(31)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(32)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(33)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(34)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(35)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(36)

Proof:

Suppose that f is uniformly continuous on(a,b). Let xn ∈ (a,b)converge to b as n→ ∞. Then{xn}is Cauchy;

hence, by Lemma 3.38, so is{f(xn)}. In particular, g(b) := lim

n→∞f(xn)

exists. This value does not change if we use a different sequence to a approximate b.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(37)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Givenǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(38)

Indeed,let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0,chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(39)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Givenǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(40)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0,chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(41)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(42)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(43)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞,we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(44)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(45)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞,we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(46)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(47)

Indeed, let yn ∈ (a,b)be another sequence that converges to b as n→ ∞. Given ǫ >0, chooseδ >0 such that (9) holds for E = (a,b). Since xnyn →0, choose NN so that nN implies|xnyn| < δ. By (9), then,|f(xn) −f(yn)| < ǫfor all nN. Taking the limit of this inequality as n → ∞, we obtain

| lim

n→∞f(xn) − lim

n→∞f(yn)| ≤ ǫ

for all ǫ >0. It follows from Theorem 1.9 that

n→∞lim f(x)= lim

n→∞f(yn).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(48)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(49)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(50)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus,f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(51)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(52)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus,f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(53)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(54)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(55)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b];hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(56)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(57)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b];hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(58)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(59)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(60)

Thus, g(b)is well defined. A similar argument defines g(a). Set g(x) =f(x)for x ∈ (a,b). Then g is defined on [a,b], satifies (11), and is continuous on[a,b]by the Sequential Characterization of Limits. Thus, f can be

“continuously extended” to g as required.

Conversely, suppose that there is a function g

continuouos on [a,b] that satifies (11). By theorem 3.39, g is uniformly continuous on [a,b]; hence, g is uniformly continuous on (a,b). We conclude that f is uniformly continuous on (a,b).2

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(61)

Example:

Prove that f(x) = (x −1)

log x is uniformly continuous on (0,1).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(62)

Example:

Prove that f(x) = (x −1)

log x is uniformly continuous on (0,1).

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

(63)

Thank you.

WEN-CHINGLIEN Advanced Calculus (I)

Figure

Updating...

References

Related subjects :
Outline : Proof: