• 沒有找到結果。

Definition. Let H be a subgroup of G. We define the quasi-level of H as ql(H) = \

g∈G

b(H, g).

Since b(H, g) = b(Hg, I2), we see that ql(H) = \

g∈G

b(Hg, I2) = b(NH, I2)

where NH is the core of H in G.

However, Example 3.2 shows that in contrast to Lemma 2.3 the intersection over g ∈ G can in general not be replaced by the intersection over a system of representatives of the cusps (even when H is a congruence subgroup).

The second equality shows that our definition of quasi-level coincides with the one we gave in [MSch2]. Actually ql(H) = b(NH, g) for any g ∈ G. But Example 3.5 shows that in contrast to Corollary 2.11 there is in general no g ∈ G for which ql(H) = b(H, g) (even when H is a congruence subgroup).

We summarize the basic properties:

Lemma 4.1.

(i) ql(H) = {d ∈ D : T (d) ∈ NH}.

(ii) ql(H) is an additive subgroup of D with the property that d ∈ ql(H), u ∈ D =⇒ u2d ∈ ql(H).

(iii) ql(H) ⊇ l(H).

(iv) ql(H) = ql(Hg) = ql(NH) = b(NH, g) for all g ∈ G.

(v) l(H) = l(Hg) = l(NH) = c(NH, g) for all g ∈ G.

(vi) l(H) is the largest D-ideal contained in ql(H).

(vii) |D : ql(H)| ≤ |SL2(D) : NH|.

For congruence subgroups we can combine Lemmas 3.4 and 4.1 to obtain the fol-lowing extension of Lemma 4.1(ii).

Lemma 4.2. Let H be a congruence subgroup and let α ∈ D be invertible mod-ulo l(H). Then

α2ql(H) ⊆ ql(H).

We will also show that when H is a congruence subgroup the inequality in Lemma 4.1(iii) becomes an equality (in “most” cases). For this purpose we require a number of preliminaries.

Lemma 4.3. Let H be a congruence subgroup of G and let l(H) = q = q1q2, where q1+ q2 = D. Then

l((H ∩ G(q1)) · G(q2)) = q2.

Proof. Let the required level be q02. Then q02 ⊇ q2. Now G(q02) ≤ (H ∩ G(q1)) · G(q2) and so

G(q1q02) = G(q1) ∩ G(q02) ≤ (H ∩ G(q1)) · G(q) ⊆ H.

Hence q ⊇ q1q02 by Corollary 1.4. The result follows.  Lemma 4.4. Let N be a normal congruence subgroup of level q = q1q2, where q1+ q2 = D. Let N0 = (N ∩ G(q1)) · G(q2) and N = N · G(q2). Then

N /N0 is a central subgroup of G/N0. Proof. Now G = G(q1) · G(q2), by Corollary 1.3. It follows that

[G, N ] = [G(q1) · G(q2), N · G(q2)] ≤ [G(q1), N ] · G(q2) ≤ N0.

The result follows. 

Our next lemma is almost certainly well-known. In the absence of a reference we provide a proof.

Lemma 4.5. Let L be a local ring for which 2 ∈ L. Then P SL2(L) has triv-ial centre.

Proof. Note that, since 2 ∈ L, the only involutions in L are ±1. Let g = α β

γ δ



∈ SL2(L).

Then, if g maps into the centre of P SL2(L), it follows that, for all x ∈ L, gT (x) = λT (x)g and gS(x) = µS(x)g,

where λ2 = µ2 = 1. If γ ∈ L, then λ = 1 and so γx = 0. Thus γ /∈ L and similarly β /∈ L. We deduce that α, δ ∈ L. From the first of the above equations it follows that α = λ(α + xγ) and hence that 2xαγ + x2γ2 = 0. The latter equation holds for x = ±1 and so 4αγ = 0. From the above γ = 0 and similarly β = 0. It then follows

from the above that α = δ, i.e. g = ±I2. 

Before coming to our next principal result we make another definition.

Definition. For a subgroup H of G = SL2(D) we define o(H) as the ideal of D generated by all elements a − d, b, c with a bc d ∈ H. Somewhat unfortunately, o(H) is sometimes called the order of H. Every matrix in H is congruent modulo o(H) to a scalar matrix xI2 for some x ∈ D, and o(H) is the smallest ideal of D with this property. Obviously

ql(H) ⊆ o(H).

Conversely, for each D-ideal q we define

Z(q) = {X ∈ G : X ≡ xI2 (mod q) for some x ∈ D}.

Then

H ≤ Z(q) ⇔ o(H) ≤ q.

So it is clear that if

G(q) ≤ H ≤ Z(q), then

ql(H) = l(H) = q.

Theorem 4.6. Let H be a congruence subgroup of SL2(D) such that l(H) = q satisfies Condition L (from the Introduction). Then

ql(H) = l(H), equivalently, the quasi-level is actually an ideal.

Proof. By Lemma 4.1(iv), (v) we may assume that H = NH (i.e. H E G). From the above it is sufficient to prove that NH ≤ Z(q), and hence that NH ≤ Z(pα), where p is any prime ideal for which α = ordp(q) > 0.

Let L denote the local ring D/pα and let

π : G −→ SL2(L),

denote the natural map. Now SL2(L) is generated by elementary matrices by [K, Theorem 1] and so (again by [K, Theorem 1])

π(G(r)) = E2(L, r) = SL2(L, r),

for all D-ideals r, where r is the image of r in L. (In particular π is an epimorphism.) Let q = q0pα. Now suppose that π(NH ∩ G(q0)) is not central in SL2(L). Then by [K, Theorem 3] the hypotheses on q and the above ensure that

G(pβ) ≤ (NH ∩ G(q0)) · G(pα).

for some β < α which contradicts Lemma 4.3 (with q2 = pα and q1 = q0). It follows that

π(NH ∩ G(q0)) ≤ {±I2}.

The map π extends to an epimorphism

π : G −→ P SL2(L).

By Lemma 4.4 π(NH) is central in P SL2(L). We now apply Lemma 4.5 to conclude that

π(NH) ≤ {±I2}.

 For normal subgroups we can reformulate Theorem 4.6 as follows.

Corollary 4.7. Let N be a normal congruence subgroup of G. If the level of N satisfies Condition L, then

b(N, g) = c(N, g),

that is, the quasi-amplitudes of N are actually the cusp amplitudes.

Proof. Since N is normal any quasi-amplitude is equal to the quasi-level and

any cusp amplitude is equal to the level. 

Remark 4.8. A word of warning is in order here. If ql(H) = l(H) for a (non-normal) congruence subgroup H and H has only one cusp, this does not imply

b(H, g) = c(H, g), not even if l(H) satisfies Condition L. See Example 3.2. Ulti-mately the problem is caused by diagonal matrices that are not central.

McQuillan [Mc, Theorem 1] has proved, for the special case D = Z, that, if N is a normal congruence subgroup of G of level q, then N ≤ Z(q), using a similar approach. We now provide a pair of examples to show that both restrictions in Theorem 4.6 are necessary.

Example 4.9. Our first example [M1, Example 2.3] shows that Theorem 4.6 can fail when q is not prime to 2. Let p be a prime D-ideal for which 2 ∈ p2. We recall Theorem 1.2 that K is normal in G.

Clearly ql(K) = {t2 + q : t ∈ p, q ∈ p4}. Now suppose that l(K) 6= p4. Then G(p3) ≤ K. Let h be a generator of p3 (mod p4). It follows that, there exists k ∈ D, such that h ≡ k2 (mod p4). We conclude that l(K) = p4.

Explicit examples that satisfy the requirement 2 ∈ p2 are, among others, D = Z[

√−2] with p = (√

−2), or to take a local example, D = Z2[√

2] with p = (√ 2).

More generally, this example actually works for any Dedekind domain of character-istic 2.

From the well-known structure of SL2(F3) it follows that there exists a normal subgroup, N , of G, containing G(q), such that

|G : N | = 9 and |N : G(q)| = 64.

Now let

M = hT (1), N i.

Since 9 = 32, M E G and |G : M | = 3. Obviously, ql(M ) contains 1. If 1 ∈ l(M ), then l(M ) = D, in which case M = G(D) = G. Thus ql(M ) 6= l(M ).

In particular, there exists a normal congruence subgroup of index 3 in SL2(F3[t]) that has level t(t + 1).

Remarks 4.11.

a) If the level of a congruence subgroup H is a prime ideal p, then ql(H) = l(H).

This follows immediately from the simplicity of the group P SL2(D/p), when

|D/p| > 3. The cases for which |D/p| ≤ 3 can be checked directly.

b) If D is any arithmetic Dedekind domain, the quasi-level of a congruence sub-group is not “ too far from” its level. For a normal congruence subsub-group N the relation between l(N ) and o(N ) is described in [M2, Theorems 3.6, 3.10 and 3.14]. See also the end of Section 3 of [M2].

For example, for a finite index subgroup H of SL2(Z[√

11]) we obtain 4ql(NH) ⊆ 4o(NH) ⊆ l(NH) ⊆ ql(NH) ⊆ o(NH)

from [M2, Theorem 3.6] since 2 is ramified and 3 is inert in Z[√

11]. Actually even 4ql(H) ( l(H) since ql(NH) = o(NH) would mean that ql(H) is an ideal and hence equal to l(H).

Our final result demonstrates that for a non-congruence subgroup there is in general almost no connection between its quasi-level and level (in contrast with Theorem 4.6). We note that there is no proper normal subgroup of SL2(k[t]) whose quasi-level is k[t]. (Since k[t] is a Euclidean ring, SL2(k[t]) is generated by T (r), S(r), where r ∈ k[t].)

Theorem 4.12. Let k be any field and let f ∈ k[t] with deg(f ) ≥ 2. Suppose that f (0) 6= 0 and, further, that f0(0) 6= 0, when deg(f ) = 2. Then there exists a normal non-congruence subgroup N of SL2(k[t]) of level (f ) with the following properties.

(i) N · SL2(k) = SL2(k[t]).

(ii) l(N ) = (f ).

(iii) ql(N ) has k-codimension 1 in k[t].

Proof. We note that, by hypothesis, t - f . We define the k-subspace Q = (f ) ⊕ kt ⊕ kt2⊕ · · · ⊕ ktd−1

where d = deg(f ). Let N = ∆(Q) be the normal subgroup of SL2(k[t]) generated by all T (q), where q ∈ Q. Since SL2(k[t]) is generated by all T (r), S(r), where r ∈ k[t], part (i) follows. In addition

ql(∆(Q)) = Q,

by [M3, Theorem 3.8]. Part (iii) follows. Suppose that l(∆(Q)) 6= (f ). Then (f ) ⊆ (h) ⊆ Q,

for some polynomial divisor h of f , with deg(h) < deg(f ). Then by the definition of Q, h, and hence f , must be divisible by t. Part (ii) follows.

Finally, suppose that N is a congruence subgroup. Since, by hypothesis t is prime to l(N ) = (f ),

t2Q ⊆ Q,

by Lemma 4.2. If deg(f ) > 2, then td∈ Q. If deg(f ) = 2, then t3 ∈ Q. Now for this case tf ∈ Q and so t2 ∈ Q, by the extra hypothesis. In either case (t) ⊆ Q, which implies that Q = k[t], a contradiction. The proof is complete.  Remarks 4.13.

a) Obviously the group N in Theorem 4.12 shows that Lemmas 3.4 and 4.2 do not hold in general for non-congruence subgroups, even if they are normal.

b) The restriction on the degree of f in Theorem 4.12 is necessary. It is well-known that, if deg(f ) ≤ 1, then every subgroup of SL2(k[t]) of level (f ) is a congruence subgroup.

c) Several versions of Theorem 4.12 are already known for subgroups of level zero.

(See Section 4 of [MSch2].)

相關文件